www.newsandletters.org











NEWS & LETTERS, December 2001

Just off the press!

The Power of Negativity: Selected Writings on the Dialectic in Hegel and Marx

by Raya Dunayevskaya

$25.95

Order from News & Letters, 36 S. Wabash, Room 1440, Chicago IL 60605

---

From the Introduction by Peter Hudis and Kevin Anderson  

I. The Present Moment

Marx's oeuvre, which many had declared obsolete, has taken on new life at the dawn of the twenty-first century because the strength of his critique of the destructive power of capital is so missed. Today's unprecedented inequities in wealth and power, accompanied by wrenching technological changes and environmental havoc, as well as monopolization and social fragmentation, are increasingly begetting the sense that the time has come to return to Marx. In a process that conjures up the spirit of the dialectic itself, the very fact which had been heralded as proving the death of Marx the universalization of capital, as it invades every corner of the earth and all spheres of everyday life has led workers as well as intellectuals, activists as well as academics, to look anew at what Marx's work means for today. This is reflected in everything from journalistic discourses on the need to face the specter of Marx to theoretical analyses on the cogency of the Marxian critique of globalized capitalism.(1) The more the globalization of capital spurs social dislocation and impoverishment, the more we can expect such appraisals of Marx in the coming period.

One surprising feature of much of the current return to Marx, however, is the relative silence on Hegel and the dialectic. This attitude has developed despite Marx's insistence in CAPITAL and other works that his method was at its core dialectical and that Hegel's dialectic was for him "the source of all dialectic."(2)

For example, in his SPECTERS OF MARX, Jacques Derrida on the one hand terms Marx's writings "urgent" for an understanding of today's globalized capitalism, while on the other distances himself from the Hegelian dialectic, which he calls an "onto-theology" and "anthropo-theology."(3) From the vantage point of the Frankfurt School, a tradition once rooted in a form of Hegelian Marxism, Jrgen Habermas rejects the Hegelian dialectic as the remnant of a romantic idealist philosophy of consciousness, and attacks Marx for remaining "tied to Hegelian logic."(4) Even Moishe Postone, a Frankfurt-trained Critical Theorist who has urged a return to Marx's critique of capital in order to comprehend the present crisis, considers the Hegelian dialectic as little more than a philosophical expression of the logic of capital.(5)

At the same time, the present moment is rife with serious studies of Hegel by non-Marxists. The past decade has experienced a veritable explosion of new works on Hegel in the Anglo-American world, as seen in such recent books as H.S. Harris's HEGEL'S LADDER, a 1,600-page study of Hegel's PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND. On a more modest, and yet significant level, new studies on Hegel by feminists, especially those from a postmodernist background, have emerged.(6) Yet instead of intersecting, the ongoing discussions of Hegel and Marx often appear as two trains passing each other in the dead of night, very nearly unnoticed by one another.

Fredric Jameson has spoken to this problem:

"This is a time when people no longer understand what dialectical thinking is or why the dialectic came into being in the first place, when they have abandoned the dialectical for less rewarding Nietzschean positions. So there is certainly a need today for a revitalized vision of the dialectic. There I would certainly not abandon Marx, but I would want to go back to Hegel for an enlargement of the way we have normally understood Marx. This is not any particularly new idea with me. Lenin had already said that no one could understand Das Kapital who had not already worked his way through Hegel's logic. . . . I think the coming years will show an unconscious need for the dialectic which some of us on the left ought to have the mission to satisfy.(7)"

The writings in this volume will, we hope, take us toward satisfying this need. At each stage in the history of Marxism, revolutionaries and theorists have felt the need to hew a path out of the seemingly insurmountable barriers facing the radical movement by turning anew to Hegel. This was true of Lenin in 1914, when he responded to the collapse of established Marxism with the outbreak of World War I by delving into Hegel's SCIENCE OF LOGIC. It was true of such diverse tendencies as the Frankfurt School and French neo-Marxists in the 1930s and 1940s, who turned to Hegel in a period defined by fascism and the rise of Stalinism. Likewise, in the 1950s, in the face of the new challenges posed by the freedom struggles of the post-World War II era, Raya Dunayevskaya (1910-87) developed the philosophy of Marxist-Humanism through a direct encounter with Hegel's dialectic.

Dunayevskaya's life and work represent a rare combination of passionate involvement in freedom struggles and intense philosophical exploration.

Born in Ukraine in 1910, she immigrated to the U.S. as a teenager, and by the mid-1920s became involved in labor, socialist, and Black liberation movements. After serving as secretary to Leon Trotsky in 1937-38, she broke with him at the time of the Hitler-Stalin Pact in 1939, and subsequently developed a theory of state-capitalism. She argued that Roosevelt's New Deal, Hitler's Germany, and especially Stalin's Russia, represented varieties of a new stage of global capitalism, one in which the fetishism of state planning was paramount.(8) This work soon brought her into a period of close collaboration with the Trinidadian Marxist and cultural critic C.L.R. James. During the 1940s, she also engaged in dialogue with a number of intellectuals of the anti-Stalinist left, such as Meyer Schapiro, and became a sharp critic of those, such as the pragmatist Sidney Hook, who strongly rejected Hegel as a reactionary thinker.

By the mid-1950s, Dunayevskaya moved in a different direction from James, as she developed a new position, rooted in a reexamination of the Hegelian underpinnings of Marx's thought, which she soon termed Marxist-Humanism.

In the late 1950s, she engaged in an extensive correspondence on dialectics with the Critical Theorist, Herbert Marcuse, and, a bit later, with Erich Fromm, another former Frankfurt School member.(9) In her MARXISM AND FREEDOM (1958), to which Marcuse contributed a critical preface, she included as appendices the first English translations of major parts of Marx's 1844 ECONOMIC AND PHILOSOPHIC MANUSCRIPTS and of Lenin's PHILOSOPHIC NOTEBOOKS.

In rethinking and extending Marx's humanist conceptions in light of the contemporary struggles of rank-and-file labor, women's liberation, African Americans, and youth from the 1950s to the 1980s, she developed an original philosophy of liberation rooted in a continuous return to the Hegelian dialectic. On the one hand, this entailed scathing critiques of anti-Hegelian Marxists such as Louis Althusser, and on the other, more sympathetic but nonetheless probing critiques of leading dialecticians, many of them Hegelian Marxists, including Marcuse, Georg Lukcs, Karl Korsch, and Theodor Adorno. In her later discussions of dialectics, she also gave prominence to what she regarded as the highly original contributions of the African liberation theorist Frantz Fanon and dissident East European Marxist humanists, as can especially be seen in her PHILOSOPHY AND REVOLUTION (1973) and ROSA LUXEMBURG, WOMEN'S LIBERATION, AND MARX'S PHILOSOPHY OF REVOLUTION (1982).

II. Contemporary Issues in Dialectical Philosophy

The need to return to the Hegelian dialectic with new eyes is no less urgent today, in light of the crisis confronting all liberation movements, whether of workers, Blacks and other minorities, women, lesbians and gays, or youth. This crisis is disclosed by the aborted and unfinished revolutions which have marked this century, from Russia 1917 to Spain 1936, China 1949, and Cuba 1959, and from Iran to Nicaragua to Grenada in the 1970s and 1980s. In particular, the experience of the Russian Revolution after 1917 suggests that even to BEGIN to hew a path out of this crisis means confronting such questions as, what happens AFTER the revolution? How can we ensure that a new form of totalitarianism or bureaucracy will not once again take over after the collapse of the old order? How can ending the division between mental and manual labor move from underlying concept to social practice?

Here is where Dunayevskaya's work as founder of Marxist-Humanism in the U.S. takes on special importance. Few thinkers in the revolutionary tradition have focused as exhaustively on these issues as Dunayevskaya, especially on the need to philosophically confront the question of what happens after the revolution. And even fewer have done so by means of a new interpretation of Hegelian dialectics.

On the whole, radical interpreters of Hegel in this century have emphasized such aspects of Hegel's thought as the master-slave dialectic and the unhappy consciousness in the PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND, or the concepts of essence, negativity, or contradiction in the SCIENCE OF LOGIC. While Dunayevskaya also addresses these issues, her core contribution to dialectics centers on what many other Marxists have ignored or rejected Hegel's concept of absolute negativity.(10) In Hegel, absolute negativity signifies not only the negation of external obstacles, but also the negation of the earlier negation of them. The power of negativity gets turned back upon the self, upon the internal as well as external barriers to self-movement. Such a negation of the negation is no mere nullity, for the positive is contained in the negative, which is the path to a new beginning.

One of Hegel's first references to absolute negativity in the Science of Logic occurs during a critique of Spinoza's notion that "every determination is a negation." Hegel considers such a stress on negativity to be a great advance over previous positions. However, this advance is not without contradiction and in Hegel's view has the drawback of dissolving into a "formless abstraction," because this type of bare negativity lacks determinateness.(11) At this point, Hegel goes beyond bare or first negativity to what he calls second or absolute negativity, with the latter containing not only a rejection of the old, but also the basis for a forward movement: "But in all this, care must be taken to distinguish between the FIRST negation as negation IN GENERAL, and the second negation, the negation of the negation: the latter is concrete, absolute negativity, just as the former on the contrary is only ABSTRACT negativity" (pp. 115-16).

If the question of absolute negativity were exhausted here, in a more or less formal process of the negation of the negation, there would be far less controversy among radical interpreters of Hegel. For example, writing more than a century ago, Friedrich Engels, whose studies of dialectics have formed the basis of most orthodox Marxist discussions of the topic ever since, did at least mention the negation of the negation. However, while extolling a formalized and sometimes scientistic notion of negation of the negation, Engels also attacks Hegel's Absolute Idea, which, he maintains, includes a notion of "the end of history" in which "the whole dogmatic content of the Hegelian system is declared to be absolute truth, in contradiction to his dialectical method, which dissolves all that is dogmatic."(12) Thus, Engels mentions the negation of the negation as a principle of the dialectic while attacking the Absolute Idea as dogmatic and even reactionary.

In contrast to Engels and most subsequent interpreters within the Marxist tradition, Dunayevskaya finds extremely important insights for a dialectics of liberation in Hegel's Absolutes, which Hegel develops in the concluding chapters of his major works. In so doing, she focuses on the chapters on Absolute Knowledge in the PHENOMENOLOGY the Absolute Idea in the SCIENCE OF LOGIC, and the Absolute Mind in the PHILOSOPHY OF MIND.

Hegel's Absolutes have been frequently dismissed not only as dogmatic, but also as closed ontology. These are interpretations which, as Dunayevskaya argues in many of the selections in this volume, are hard to maintain once one examines Hegel's actual texts. This can be seen from a few representative passages from the chapter on the Absolute Idea with which Hegel concludes the Science of Logic. Hegel begins his discussion by stating that the Absolute Idea is "the identity of the theoretical and the practical idea," thereby holding to a notion of practice as well as of theory at the very point where some have seen only a flight into an abstract universal. A few lines further in this same passage, Hegel also writes that "the Absolute Idea...contains within itself the highest degree of opposition" (p. 824). Here, at least, Hegel rejects the notion of an oppositionless totality which has absorbed all negativity and particularity, as is so often charged.

Some pages later, at the conclusion of the chapter, Hegel writes of the Absolute Idea as an "absolute liberation," as a dialectic of freedom in which "no transition takes place" (p. 843). The human spirit now moves toward liberation, having already worked through the myriad obstacles which lay in wait for freedom in the previous 800 pages of his work.

Dunayevskaya's focus on Hegel's Absolutes countered the traditional Marxist view of them as a closed ontology in which all particularities and difference are effaced in the name of an abstract unity. As early as her initial studies on dialectics in the late 1940s, she emphasized the sheer genius of [Hegel's] language which defines identity as unseparated difference (see the appendix to this volume, part 4).

Nor was she attracted to Hegel's Absolutes out of an affinity with Lukcs's emphasis on totality. Throughout her work, from her Letters on Hegel's Absolutes of 1953 through MARXISM AND FREEDOM (1958), PHILOSOPHY AND REVOLUTION (1973) and ROSA LUXEMBURG, WOMEN'S LIBERATION, AND MARX'S PHILOSOPHY OF REVOLUTION (1982), she saw in Hegel's Absolutes the categories of freedom, of subjectivity, of reason, the logic of a movement by which humanity makes itself free. As she put it in chapter 1 of PHILOSOPHY AND REVOLUTION, her most sustained and important discussion of Hegel,

"Precisely where Hegel sounds most abstract, seems to close the shutters tight against the whole movement of history, there he lets the lifeblood of the dialectic absolute negativity pour in. It is true that Hegel writes as if the resolution of opposing live forces can be overcome by a mere thought transcendence. But he has, by bringing oppositions to their most logical extreme, opened new paths, a new relationship of theory t o practice, which Marx worked out as a totally new relationship of philosophy to revolution. Today's revolutionaries turn their backs on this at their peril" (p. 34).

(To be continued next issue)

NOTES

1. The protests against the World Trade Organization in Seattle at the end of 1999, and the demonstrations in Washington, D.C. against the International Monetary Fund and World Bank in April 2000, have proved of special importance in having many turn with new eyes to Marx's critique of capital.

2. Karl Marx, CAPITAL, Vol. I, trans. by Ben Fowkes (London: Pelican, 1976), pp. 102, 744.

3. Jacques Derrida, SPECTERS OF MARX, trans. by Peggy Kamuf (New York: Routledge, 1993), pp. 13, 144.

4. Jrgen Habermas, THE THEORY OF COMMUNICATIVE ACTION, Vol. 2, trans. by Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon, 1987), p. 338.

5. Moishe Postone, TIME, LABOR, AND SOCIAL DOMINATION (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993).

6. See especially Dianne Coole, NEGATIVITY AND POLITICS (London: Routledge, 2000); Judith Butler's Introduction to a new edition of SUBJECTS OF DESIRE: HEGELIAN REFLECTIONS IN 20TH CENTURY FRANCE (New York: Columbia University Press, 1999); and Toula Nicolapoulos and George Vassilacopoulos, HEGEL AND THE LOGICAL STRUCTURE OF LOVE (London: Ashgate Publishing Company, 1999).

7. Interview with Fredric Jameson, LUKCS AFTER COMMUNIISM, INTERVIEWS WITH CONTEMPORARY INTELLECTUALS, in Eva L. Corredor (Durham and London: Duke University Press, 1997), p. 93. We should add that in works such as DIALECTICAL INVESTIGATIONS (New York: Routledge, 1993), Bertell Ollman has steadfastly defended the dialectical core of Marxism throughout the recent period, often in the face of sharp opposition to dialectical thought.

8. Many of these writings have been recently published in THE MARXIST-HUMANIST THEORY OF STATE-CAPITALISM: SELECTED WRITINGS BY RAYA DUNAYEVSKAYA (Chicago: News and Letters, 1992), with an Introduction by Peter Hudis.

9. Some of her correspondence with James, Marcuse, and Fromm is included in this volume. Most of her other correspondence and writings have been gathered in THE RAYA DUNAYEVSKAYA COLLECTION: MARXIST-HUMANISMÑA HALF-CENTURY OF ITS WORLD DEVELOPMENT, on deposit at Wayne State University Archives of Labor History and Urban Affairs in Detroit, Michigan.

10. For some discussions of Dunayevskaya's standpoint on Hegel, see Patricia Altenbernd Johnson, Women's Liberation: Following Dunayevskaya in Practicing Dialectics,Ó QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF IDEOLOGY, Vol. 13: 4 (1989), pp. 65-74; Thomas M. Jeannot, Raya Dunayevskaya's Conception of Ultimate Reality and Meaning, JOURNAL OF ULTIMATE REALITY AND MEANING, Vol. 22:4 (1999), pp. 276-93. See also the entry for Dunayevskaya in WOMEN BUILDING CHICAGO, 1790-1990: A BIBLIOGRAPHICAL DICTIONARY, ed. by Rima Lunin Schultz and Adele Hast (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001).

11. G. W. F. Hegel, SCIENCE OF LOGIC, trans. by A. V. Miller (New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1969), p. 113. Subsequent pages references are directly in the text.

12. Engels, LUDWIG FEUERBACK AND THE END OF CLASSICAL GERMAN PHILOSOPHY, Marx-Engels COLLECTED WORKS, Vol. 26 (New York: International Publishers, 1990), pp. 360-61.

Return to top


Home l News & Letters Newspaper l Back issues l News and Letters Committees l Dialogues l Raya Dunayevskaya l Contact us l Search

Subscribe to News & Letters

Published by News and Letters Committees
Designed and maintained by  Internet Horizons